The 2016 Nobel Prize: Incentives, Property Rights, and Ownership
The 2016 Nobel
Prize in economics was awarded today to Oliver Hart and Bengt
Holmström, two of the most eminent economists specializing in the
analysis of contracting and organizational structure. Hart, a British economist
who teaches at Harvard, and Holmström, originally from Finland and now teaching
at MIT, are leading practitioners of the formal, mathematical analysis of
firms, contracts, and organizations. Hart is best known for his contributions
to the “incomplete-contracting” or “property-rights” approach to the firm,
while Holmström is considered the founder of modern principal-agent theory.
Both have long been considered frontrunners for the prize (Paul Krugman tweeted that the two are so obviously
deserving his first thought was, “didn’t they have it already?” — something
said about Krugman’s own Nobel by No One Ever).
As Nicolai Foss
pointed out in an insightful 1994 article,
and I have also discussed in my own work, the
Austrian economists anticipated many of the points in the modern economics of
contracting and organization. Take principal-agent theory. While Mises’s 1920 article on socialist economic
calculation offers the definitive
statement on why a rational allocation of resources is impossible under common
ownership of the means of production, it is sometimes forgotten that Mises 1922 book Socialism, which includes the calculation
argument, also includes a lengthy discussion of incentives under socialism, and
Hayek discusses the problem in detail in his contribution to Collectivist Economic Planning. Mises also addresses the separation of
ownership and control in Human Action.
The Principal-agent
Problem
Holmström is
best-known for a specific interpretation of the principal-agent problem
(articulated in his most-cited article, “Moral Hazard in Teams”).
Holmström examines a situation in which one party (the “principal”) has some
task to be performed, but must hire another party (the “agent”) to perform the
task. Performing the task is costly to the agent, so the principal must provide
some incentives to get the agent to do what the principal wants. If the
principal cannot observe or understand the agent’s actions directly — which is
plausible, otherwise the principal could simply perform the task — then an
incentive contract based on some observable, but noisy signal of output is
problematic, because it exposes the agent to risks related to the noisiness of
the signal. (For example, incentivizing salaried managers by giving them stock
options helps to align their incentives with those of shareholders, but exposes
them to the risk of market fluctuations that are caused by the Fed, by the actions
of other firms, or other forces beyond their control.) Hence principals face a
specific tradeoff between providing incentives for agents (by using
performance-based pay) and insuring agents against risks beyond their control
(by using fixed salaries). Exactly how this tradeoff should be managed depends
on the particulars of the situation.
While the Austrians
did not explore the specific aspects of the agency problem highlighted by
Holmström — this tradeoff between incentives and insurance — they did recognize
the importance of the agency problem, and Mises in particular offered a nuanced
discussion of various means by which principals mitigate agency problems,
anticipating a well-known argument of Henry Manne (see my discussion here). Austrian
ideas about entrepreneurship, heterogeneous capital, and tacit knowledge can
also improve our understanding of agency problems (Foss et
al. 2007). (For further discussion of Austrian economics and agency
problems see Padilla
2003 and Hülsmann 2008).
Property Rights and
Ownership
While entrepreneurship
does not get a mention in the Nobel citation, Hart’s insights on property
rights and ownership have greatly influenced my own understanding of the
entrepreneurial function. Following Frank Knight, I have argued that
entrepreneurs establish firms because entrepreneurial judgment is
non-contractible. In other words, an entrepreneur’s idiosyncratic understanding
of the future — what Knight and Mises call judgment — can only be expressed through ownership of
resources. Ownership provides the ultimate control of productive resources,
meaning that owners get the final say in how resources will be used. A resource
owner can contract for advice (e.g., by hiring a consultant), but only the
owner can make the final decisions about deploying resources (the owner chooses
whether or not to hire a consultant, which consultant to hire, and whether to
act upon the consultant’s advice). Judgment is the act of exercising this form
of control over resources. In other words, there are markets for assets, but
not markets for judgment, because judgment implies the right to control an
asset. To exercise judgment, the entrepreneur most own assets, i.e., must
establish or maintain a firm. (This is a somewhat different perspective on entrepreneurship than Israel Kirzner’s
well-known approach.)
Hart’s work with
Sanford Grossman and with John
Moore (hence, the
“Grossman-Hart-Moore” theory of the firm) is based on a particular concept of
asset ownership. Ownership, in this approach, is defined as residual rights of
control — i.e., the right to decide how an asset will be used in situations not
covered by prior agreement. In a world of perfect certainty (akin to Mises’s
evenly rotating economy), individuals could write very complex and detailed
contracts about how various resources will be used under particular
circumstances. With contracts like these, “ownership” is vague and
indeterminate; it doesn’t matter who has formal title to an asset because the
asset will be used in exactly the same way regardless.
In the real world of
uncertainty, however, such contracts are impossible, because we cannot anticipate
every potential future event and agree in advance on what we would do. In other
words, all feasible contracts are “incomplete,” meaning that they contain some
omissions or gaps. Property rights are thus necessary to fill in the gaps. If
party A is the owner of the asset, then even though party B may have certain
contractual rights to use the asset in particular ways, if an unforeseen
contingency arises, the decision is made by party A. This is a useful and
parsimonious way to think about ownership.
In Hart’s work (his 1995 book is the most accessible treatment), these
ownership incentives are important because they affect what kinds of investments
parties are willing to make in creating and maintaining specialized assets. I
find their theory of the firm insightful, though there are many potential
problems with the details. More generally, though, their understanding of
ownership helps clarify some ambiguities about property rights. For example,
people often confuse residual control rights – the right to determine how a
resource will be used when unanticipated circumstances arise – with residual
income rights. But residual income rights can be partly delegated to
non-owners; I can own a restaurant collect a fixed fee, while letting the
manager keep the net profit. That does not make the manager the owner of the
firm, because he cannot change this arrangement, or sell the restaurant, or do
a host of other things without my permission.
Mises works with a
similar definition: “Ownership means full control of the services that can be
derived from a good” (Human Action, p. 678). He goes on in that passage to distinguish this
“catallactic” definition with the legal definition; i.e., ownership for
economics means de facto control, not de jure control. (Under interventionism,
as Mises points out, the control of legal owners is severely circumscribed by
government policy.) Mises also contrasts the ultimatecontrol afforded by ownership with the
proximate, day-to-day control rights that can be delegated to non-owners, in
the context of the principal-agent problem in corporations: “The general
direction of a corporation's conduct of business is exercised by the
stockholders and their elected mandataries, the directors. The directors
appoint and discharge the managers. ... A successful corporation is ultimately
never controlled by hired managers (Human Action, p. 304).” As I have emphasized in my own work,
Mises always associated entrepreneurship exercised under uncertainty with
resource ownership. Outside the imaginary construction of the evenly rotating
economy, “A capitalist is always also virtually an entrepreneur and speculator”
(Human
Action, p. 254).
Bottom Line
My overall reaction to
this year’s Nobel is positive. As with Oliver Williamson’s work,
there is much in the writings of Holmström and Hart for Austrian economists to
admire. Unlike Williamson, they are less explicitly influenced by thinkers such
as Hayek, and they write in the style of modern mathematical economists. But
their work is worth careful study and has interesting implications for
Austrians — something I would definitely not say about all the recent
Laureates.
https://mises.org/blog/2016-nobel-prize-incentives-property-rights-and-ownership
Comments
Post a Comment